I can hardly do better than go back to the Greeks. I will state and prove two of the famous theorems of Greek mathematics. They are ‘simple’ theorems, simple both in idea and in execution,but there is no doubt at all about their being theorems of the highest class. Each is as fresh and significant as when it has discovered—two thousand years have not written a wrinkle on either of them. Finally, both the statements and the proofs can be mastered in an hour by any intelligent reader, however slender his mathematical equipment.I love this kind of stuff.
1. The first is Euclid’s proof of the existence of an infinity of prime numbers. The prime numbers or primes are the numbers which cannot be resolved into smaller factors $$2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, 23, 29,...$$ Thus \(37\) and \(317\) are prime. The primes are the material out of which all numbers are built up by multiplication: thus \(666 = 2 ⋅ 3 ⋅ 3 ⋅ 37\). Every number which is not prime itself is divisible by at least one prime (usually, of course, by several). We have to prove that there are infinitely many primes, i.e. that the series never comes to an end. Let us suppose that it does, and that \(2, 3, 5, ... , P\) is the complete series (so that \(P\) is the largest prime); and let us, on this hypothesis, consider the number \(Q\) defined by the formula $$Q = (2 ⋅ 3 ⋅ 5 ⋅ 3 ⋅..⋅ P) + 1$$ It is plain that \(Q\) is not divisible by and of \(2, 3, 5, ... , P\); for it leaves the remainder \(1\) when divided by any one of these numbers. But, if not itself prime, it is divisible by some prime, and therefore there is a prime (which may be \(Q\) itself) greater than any of them. This contradicts our hypothesis, that there is no prime greater than \(P\) ; and therefore this hypothesis is false.
The proof is by reductio ad absurdum, and reductio ad absurdum, which Euclid loved so much, is one of a mathematician’s finest weapons. It is a far finer gambit than any chess gambit: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game.
2. My second example is Pythagoras’s proof of the ‘irrationality’ of \(\sqrt{2}\). A ‘rational number’ is fraction \(\frac{a}{b}\), where \(a\) and \(b\) are integers: we may suppose that \(a\) and \(b\) have no common factor, since if they had we could remove it. To say that ‘\(\sqrt{2}\) is irrational’ is merely another way of saying that \(2\) cannot be expressed in the form \((\frac{a}{b})^2\); and this is the same as saying that the equation $$a^2 = 2b^2$$ cannot be satisfied by integral values of \(a\) and \(b\) which have no common factor. This is a theorem of pure arithmetic, which does not demand any knowledge of ‘irrational numbers’ or depend on any theory about their nature. We argue again by reductio ad absurdum; we suppose that the equation is true, \(a\) and \(b\) being integers without any common factor. It follows that \(a^2\) is even (since \(2b^2\) is divisible by \(2\)), and therefore that \(a\) is even (since the square of an odd number is odd). If \(a\) is even then $$a = 2c$$ for some integral value of \(c\); and therefore $$2b^2 = a^2 = (2c)^2 = 4c^2$$ or $$b^2 = 2c^2$$ Hence \(b^2\) is even, and therefore (for the same reason as before) \(b\) is even. That is to say, \(a\) and \(b\) are both even, and so have common factor \(2\). This contradicts our hypothesis, and therefore the hypothesis is false.
It follows from Pythagoras’s theorem that the diagonal of a square is incommensurable with the side (that their ratio is not a rational number, that there is no unit of which both are integral multiples). For if we take the side as our unit of length, and the length of the diagonal is \(d\), then, by a very familiar theorem also ascribed to Pythagoras, $$d^2 = 1^2 + 1^2 = 2$$ So that \(d\) cannot be a rational number.
August 20, 2014
A Mathematician's Apology
I have just read the awesome book written by G. C. Hardy in 1940: "A Mathematician's Apology". It is a must read. Among other things, he talks about the many aspects of Mathematics and I found there two beautiful theorems which he considers (and I agree) that are accessible to anyone. These two theorems are trustful witnesses of the glory and beauty of Mathematics.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment